Kandee Lopes : This Is An Un Official Fan Site Tribute
Kandee Lopes Kandee-Lops, Kandee Loupes, Kandee Lops, Kandee
Porn Queen Actress Superstar


Kandee Lopes

Movie Title Year Distributor Notes Rev Formats Bad Mama Jama Returns 1999 Video Team 1 DO Beauty and the Feast 2010 Eruptions DO Big Black Bang 1999 Seduction DO Big Boob Bangeroo 13 1999 Totally Tasteless Facial DRO Big Fat F.N. Tits 1 1999 Extreme Associates Anal Facial 1 D Black Knockers 58 1999 Visual Images Bodacious Video Magazine 1 1998 Bodacious Entertainment Five Tons of Black Fun 1998 Filmco Releasing Get Jiggy Miss Piggy 1999 Totally Tasteless DRO Natural Wonders of the World 3 1998 Blue Coyote Pictures 1 DO Nature's Breast 2001 Big Top Video DO Roly Poly Gang Bang 3 1999 Heatwave DO Suck It Out 11 2014 Sinister TV In mathematics, logic, and computer science, a type theory is any of a class of formal systems, some of which can serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundation for all mathematics. In type theory, every "term" has a "type" and operations are restricted to terms of a certain type. Type theory is closely related to (and in some cases overlaps with) type systems, which are a programming language feature used to reduce bugs. Type theory was created to avoid paradoxes in formal logics and rewrite systems.
Two well-known type theories that can serve as mathematical foundations are Alonzo Church's typed ?-calculus and Per Martin-Löf's intuitionistic type theory. Contents 1 History 2 Basic concepts 3 Difference from set theory 4 Optional features 4.1 Normalization 4.2 Dependent types 4.3 Equality types 4.4 Inductive types 4.5 Universe types 4.6 Computational component 5 Type theories 5.1 Major 5.2 Minor 5.3 Active 6 Practical impact 6.1 Programming languages 6.2 Mathematical foundations 6.3 Proof assistants 6.4 Linguistics 6.5 Social sciences 7 Relation to category theory 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Further reading 12 External links History Main article: History of type theory Between 1902 and 1908 Bertrand Russell proposed various "theories of type" in response to his discovery that Gottlob Frege's version of naive set theory was afflicted with Russell's paradox. By 1908 Russell arrived at



a "ramified" theory of types together with an "axiom of reducibility" both of which featured prominently in Whitehead and Russell's Principia Mathematica published between 1910 and 1913. They attempted to resolve Russell's paradox by first creating a hierarchy of types, then assigning each concrete mathematical (and possibly other) entity to a type. Entities of a given type are built exclusively from entities of those types that are lower in their hierarchy, thus preventing an entity from being assigned to itself. In the 1920s, Leon Chwistek and Frank P. Ramsey proposed an unramified type theory, now known as the "theory of simple types" or "simple type theory", which collapsed the hierarchy of the types in the earlier ramified theory and as such did not require the axiom of reducibility. The common usage of "type theory" is when those types are used with a term rewrite system. The most famous early example is Alonzo Church's simply typed lambda calculus. Church's theory of types[1] helped the formal system avoid the Kleene–Rosser paradox that afflicted the original untyped lambda calculus. Church demonstrated that it could serve as a foundation of mathematics and it was referred to as a higher-order logic. Some other type theories include Per Martin-Löf's intuitionistic type theory, which has been the foundation used in some areas of constructive mathematics. Thierry Coquand's calculus of constructions and its derivatives are the foundation used by Coq, Lean, and others. The field is an area of active research, as demonstrated by homotopy type theory. Basic concepts In a system of type theory, each term has a type. For example, {\displaystyle 4}4, {\displaystyle 2+2}2+2, and {\displaystyle 2\cdot 2}{\displaystyle 2\cdot 2} are all separate terms with the type {\displaystyle \mathrm {nat} }\mathrm {nat} for natural numbers. Traditionally, the term is followed by a colon and its type, such as {\displaystyle 2:\mathrm {nat} }2:\mathrm {nat} - this means that the number {\displaystyle 2}2 is of type {\displaystyle \mathrm {nat} }\mathrm {nat} . Type theories have explicit computation and it is encoded in rules for rewriting terms. These are called conversion rules or, if the rule only works in one direction, a reduction rule. For example, {\displaystyle 2+2}2+2 and {\displaystyle 4}4 are syntactically different terms, but the former reduces to the latter. This reduction is written {\displaystyle 2+2\twoheadrightarrow 4}{\displaystyle 2+2\twoheadrightarrow 4}. Functions in type theory have a special reduction rule: the argument to the function is substituted for every instance of the parameter in the function definition. Let's say the function {\displaystyle \mathrm {double} }{\displaystyle \mathrm {double} } is defined as {\displaystyle \lambda x.x+x}{\displaystyle \lambda x.x+x} (using Church's lambda notation) or {\displaystyle x\mapsto x+x}{\displaystyle x\mapsto x+x} (using a more modern notation). Then, the function call {\displaystyle \mathrm {double} \ 2}{\displaystyle \mathrm {double} \ 2} would be reduced by substituting {\displaystyle 2}2 for every {\displaystyle x}x in the function definition. Thus, {\displaystyle \mathrm {double} \ 2\twoheadrightarrow 2+2}{\displaystyle \mathrm {double} \ 2\twoheadrightarrow 2+2}. The type of a function is denoted with an arrow {\displaystyle \to }\to from the parameter type to the function's return type. Thus, {\displaystyle \mathrm {double} :\mathrm {nat} \to \mathrm {nat} }{\displaystyle \mathrm {double} :\mathrm {nat} \to \mathrm {nat} }. Calling or "applying" a function to an argument may be written with or without parentheses, so {\displaystyle \mathrm {double} (2)}{\displaystyle \mathrm {double} (2)} or {\displaystyle \mathrm {double} \ 2}{\displaystyle \mathrm {double} \ 2}. Omitting parentheses is more common, because multiple argument functions can be defined using currying. Difference from set theory There are many different set theories and many different systems of type theory, so what follows are generalizations. Set theory is built on top of logic. It requires a separate system like predicate logic underneath it. In type theory, concepts like "and" and "or" can be encoded as types in the type theory itself. In set theory, an element is not restricted to one set. In type theory, terms (generally) belong to only one type. (Where a subset would be used, type theory tends to use a predicate function that returns true if the term is in the subset and returns false if the value is not. The union of two types can be defined as a new type called a sum type, which contains new terms.) Set theory usually encodes numbers as sets. (0 is the empty set, 1 is a set containing the empty set, etc. See Set-theoretic definition of natural numbers.) Type theory can encode numbers as functions using Church encoding or more naturally as inductive types. Inductive types create new constants for the successor function and zero, closely resembling Peano's axioms. Type theory has a simple connection to constructive mathematics through the BHK interpretation. It can be connected to logic by the Curry–Howard isomorphism. And some type theories are closely connected to Category theory. Optional features Normalization The term {\displaystyle 2+1}2+1 reduces to {\displaystyle 3}3. Since {\displaystyle 3}3 cannot be reduced further, it is called a normal form. A system of type theory is said to be strongly normalizing if all terms have a normal form and any order of reductions reaches it. Weakly normalizing systems have a normal form but some orders of reductions may loop forever and never reach it. For a normalizing system, some borrow the word element from set theory and use it to refer to all closed terms that can reduce to the same normal form. A closed term has no parameters. (A term like {\displaystyle x+1}x+1 with its parameter {\displaystyle x}x is called an open term.) Thus, {\displaystyle 2+1}2+1 and {\displaystyle 3+0}3+0 may be different terms but they are both from the element {\displaystyle 3}3. Convertibility is a similar idea which works for both open and closed terms. Two terms are convertible if they can be reduced to the same term. Confluent and weakly normalizing systems can test if two terms are convertible by checking if they both reduce to the same normal form. Dependent types Main article: Dependent types A dependent type is a type that depends on a term or another type. Thus, the type returned by a function may depend on the argument to the function. For example, a list of {\displaystyle \mathrm {nat} }\mathrm {nat} s of length 4 may be a different type than a list of {\displaystyle \mathrm {nat} }\mathrm {nat} s of length 5. In a type theory with dependent types, it is possible to define a function that takes a parameter "n" and returns a list containing "n" zeros. Calling the function with 4 would produce a term with a different type than if the function was called with 5. Dependent types play a central role in intuitionistic type theory and in the design of functional programming languages like Idris, ATS, Agda and Epigram. Equality types Many systems of type theory have a type that represents equality of types and of terms. This type is different from convertibility, and is often denoted propositional equality. In intuitionistic type theory, the equality type (also called the identity type) is known as {\displaystyle I}I for identity. There is a type {\displaystyle I\ A\ a\ b}I\ A\ a\ b when {\displaystyle A}A is a type and {\displaystyle a}a and {\displaystyle b}b are both terms of type {\displaystyle A}A. A term of type {\displaystyle I\ A\ a\ b}I\ A\ a\ b is interpreted as meaning that {\displaystyle a}a is equal to {\displaystyle b}b. In practice, it is possible to build a type {\displaystyle I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 4}I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 4 but there will not exist a term of that type. In intuitionistic type theory, new terms of equality start with reflexivity. If {\displaystyle 3}3 is a term of type {\displaystyle \mathrm {nat} }\mathrm {nat} , then there exists a term of type {\displaystyle I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 3}I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 3. More complicated equalities can be created by creating a reflexive term and then doing a reduction on one side. So if {\displaystyle 2+1}2+1 is a term of type {\displaystyle \mathrm {nat} }\mathrm {nat} , then there is a term of type {\displaystyle I\ \mathrm {nat} \ (2+1)\ (2+1)}I\ \mathrm {nat} \ (2+1)\ (2+1) and, by reduction, generate a term of type {\displaystyle I\ \mathrm {nat} \ (2+1)\ 3}I\ \mathrm {nat} \ (2+1)\ 3. Thus, in this system, the equality type denotes that two values of the same type are convertible by reductions. Having a type for equality is important because it can be manipulated inside the system. There is usually no judgement to say two terms are not equal; instead, as in the Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation, we map {\displaystyle \neg (a=b)}\neg (a=b) to {\displaystyle (a=b)\to \bot }(a=b)\to \bot , where {\displaystyle \bot }\bot is the bottom type having no values. There exists a term with type {\displaystyle (I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 4)\to \bot }(I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 4)\to \bot , but not one of type {\displaystyle (I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 3)\to \bot }(I\ \mathrm {nat} \ 3\ 3)\to \bot . Homotopy type theory differs from intuitionistic type theory mostly by its handling of the equality type. Inductive types Main article: Inductive type A system of type theory requires some basic terms and types to operate on. Some systems build them out of functions using Church encoding. Other systems have inductive types: a set of base types and a set of type constructors that generate types with well-behaved properties. For example, certain recursive functions called on inductive types are guaranteed to terminate. Coinductive types are infinite data types created by giving a function that generates the next element(s). See Coinduction and Corecursion. Induction-induction is a feature for declaring an inductive type and a family of types which depends on the inductive type. Induction recursion allows a wider range of well-behaved types, allowing the type and recursive functions operating on it to be defined at the same time. Universe types Types were created to prevent paradoxes, such as Russell's paradox. However, the motives that lead to those paradoxes—being able to say things about all types—still exist. So, many type theories have a "universe type", which contains all other types (and not itself). In systems where you might want to say something about universe types, there is a hierarchy of universe types, each containing the one below it in the hierarchy. The hierarchy is defined as being infinite, but statements must only refer to a finite number of universe levels. Type universes are particularly tricky in type theory. The initial proposal of intuitionistic type theory suffered from Girard's paradox. Computational component Many systems of type theory, such as the simply-typed lambda calculus, intuitionistic type theory, and the calculus of constructions, are also programming languages. That is, they are said to have a "computational component". The computation is the reduction of terms of the language using rewriting rules. A system of type theory that has a well-behaved computational component also has a simple connection to constructive mathematics through the BHK interpretation. Non-constructive mathematics in these systems is possible by adding operators on continuations such as call with current continuation. However, these operators tend to break desirable properties such as canonicity and parametricity. Type theories Major Simply typed lambda calculus which is a higher-order logic; intuitionistic type theory; system F; LF is often used to define other type theories; calculus of constructions and its derivatives. Minor Automath; ST type theory; UTT (Lao's Unified Theory of dependent Types) some forms of combinatory logic; others defined in the lambda cube; others under the name typed lambda calculus; others under the name pure type system. Active Homotopy type theory is being researched. Practical impact Programming languages Main article: Type system There is extensive overlap and interaction between the fields of type theory and type systems. Type systems are a programming language feature designed to identify bugs. Any static program analysis, such as the type checking algorithms in the semantic analysis phase of compiler, has a connection to type theory. A prime example is Agda, a programming language which uses UTT (Lao's Unified Theory of dependent Types) for its type system. The programming language ML was developed for manipulating type theories (see LCF) and its own type system was heavily influenced by them. Mathematical foundations [icon] This section needs expansion. You can help by adding to it. (May 2008) The first computer proof assistant, called Automath, used type theory to encode mathematics on a computer. Martin-Löf specifically developed intuitionistic type theory to encode all mathematics to serve as a new foundation for mathematics. There is ongoing research into mathematical foundations using homotopy type theory. Mathematicians working in category theory already had difficulty working with the widely accepted foundation of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. This led to proposals such as Lawvere's Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets (ETCS).[2] Homotopy type theory continues in this line using type theory. Researchers are exploring connections between dependent types (especially the identity type) and algebraic topology (specifically homotopy). Proof assistants Main article: Proof assistant Much of the current research into type theory is driven by proof checkers, interactive proof assistants, and automated theorem provers. Most of these systems use a type theory as the mathematical foundation for encoding proofs, which is not surprising, given the close connection between type theory and programming languages: LF is used by Twelf, often to define other type theories; many type theories which fall under higher-order logic are used by the HOL family of provers and PVS; computational type theory is used by NuPRL; calculus of constructions and its derivatives are used by Coq, Matita, and Lean; UTT (Lao's Unified Theory of dependent Types) is used by Agda which is both a programming language and proof assistant Many type theories are supported by LEGO and Isabelle. Isabelle also supports foundations besides type theories, such as ZFC. Mizar is an example of a proof system that only supports set theory. Linguistics Type theory is also widely used in formal theories of semantics of natural languages, especially Montague grammar and its descendants. In particular, categorial grammars and pregroup grammars extensively use type constructors to define the types (noun, verb, etc.) of words. The most common construction takes the basic types {\displaystyle e}e and {\displaystyle t}t for individuals and truth-values, respectively, and defines the set of types recursively as follows: if {\displaystyle a}a and {\displaystyle b}b are types, then so is {\displaystyle \langle a,b\rangle }\langle a,b\rangle ; nothing except the basic types, and what can be constructed from them by means of the previous clause are types. A complex type {\displaystyle \langle a,b\rangle }\langle a,b\rangle is the type of functions from entities of type {\displaystyle a}a to entities of type {\displaystyle b}b. Thus one has types like {\displaystyle \langle e,t\rangle }\langle e,t\rangle which are interpreted as elements of the set of functions from entities to truth-values, i.e. indicator functions of sets of entities. An expression of type {\displaystyle \langle \langle e,t\rangle ,t\rangle }\langle \langle e,t\rangle ,t\rangle is a function from sets of entities to truth-values, i.e. a (indicator function of a) set of sets. This latter type is standardly taken to be the type of natural language quantifiers, like everybody or nobody (Montague 1973, Barwise and Cooper 1981). Social sciences Gregory Bateson introduced a theory of logical types into the social sciences; his notions of double bind and logical levels are based on Russell's theory of types. Relation to category theory Although the initial motivation for category theory was far removed from foundationalism, the two fields turned out to have deep connections. As John Lane Bell writes: "In fact categories can themselves be viewed as type theories of a certain kind; this fact alone indicates that type theory is much more closely related to category theory than it is to set theory." In brief, a category can be viewed as a type theory by regarding its objects as types (or sorts), i.e. "Roughly speaking, a category may be thought of as a type theory shorn of its syntax." A number of significant results follow in this way:[3] cartesian closed categories correspond


nude bikini pics clinton photos chelsea pictures desnuda fotos naked laura porn free porno fan and linda video site lisa kelly playboy topless lolo joan xxx official sex traci ferrari lords eva photo the nue tube pic videos sexy smith ana leah welch lovelace you remini club loren giacomo karen elizabeth carangi fake julia trinity ava kate fenech dana pozzi images gallery edwige moana victoria kristel joanna pornstar foto sylvia rachel pamela principal clips movies lauren shania valerie fabian collins nia rio del robin rhodes hart jane stevens measurements susan taylor jenny sanchez moore lane antonelli lancaume nancy roselyn emily hartley boobs brooke angie kim web demi bonet carrie allen grant hot esther deborah with braga jones fansite yates freeones
lee heather tina inger severance christina louise lopez gina wallpaper nacked ann film nackt fisher carey corinne shue ass vancamp clery model shannon elisabeth panties biografia angelina sofia erin monroe dazza charlene janet doris vanessa anna belinda reguera diane paula fucking scene peeples sonia shauna autopsy monica sharon patricia alicia plato bardot
melissa movie picture cynthia nicole maria star nina julie mary gemser naomi williams torrent nuda barbara twain anderson gia nudes fakes larue pussy actress upskirt san raquel jennifer tits mariah meg sandra big michelle roberts marie lumley tewes clip salma vergara jada cristal day shields cassidy sandrelli penthouse dickinson goldie nud angel brigitte drew fucked amanda shemale olivia website milano ellen ellison vidcaps hayek stone download carmen bessie swimsuit vera zeta locklear shirley anal gray cindy marilyn connie kayla sucking streep cock jensen john tiffani stockings hawn for weaver rue barrymore catherine bellucci rebecca bondage feet applegate jolie sigourney wilkinson nipples juliet revealing teresa magazine kennedy ashley what bio biography agutter wood her jordan hill com jessica pornos blowjob
lesbian nued grace hardcore regera palmer asia theresa leeuw heaton juhi alyssa pinkett rene actriz black vicky jamie ryan gillian massey short shirtless scenes maggie dreyfus lynne mpegs melua george thiessen jean june crawford alex natalie bullock playmate berry andrews maren kleevage quennessen pix hair shelley tiffany gunn galleries from russo dhue lebrock leigh fuck stefania tilton laurie russell vids bessie swimsuit vera zeta shirley locklear anal gray cindy marilyn connie kayla sucking streep cock jensen john tiffani stockings hawn for weaver rue catherine barrymore bellucci rebecca bondage feet applegate jolie george thiessen jean june crawford alex sigourney wilkinson nipples juliet revealing teresa magazine kennedy ashley what bio biography agutter jordan wood her hill com jessica pornos blowjob lesbian nued grace
hardcore regera palmer asia theresa leeuw heaton juhi alyssa pinkett rene actriz black vicky rutherford lohan winslet spungen shawnee swanson newton hannah leslie silverstone did frann wallpapers kidman louis kristy valeria lang fiorentino deanna rita hillary katie granny girls megan tori paris arquette amber sue escort chawla dorothy jessie anthony courtney shot sites kay meryl judy candice desnudo wallace gertz show teen savannah busty schneider glass thong spears young erika aniston stiles capshaw loni imagenes von myspace jena daryl girl hotmail nicola savoy
garr bonnie sexe play adriana donna angelique love actor mitchell unger sellecca adult hairstyles malone teri hayworth lynn harry kara rodriguez films welles peliculas kaprisky uschi blakely halle lindsay miranda jami jamie ryan gillian massey short scenes shirtless maggie dreyfus lynne mpegs melua natalie bullock playmate berry andrews maren kleevage quennessen pix hair shelley tiffany gunn









www.shanagrant.com

Shauna Grant The Last Porn Queen